Tuesday, December 18, 2012

The dissatisfaction with reasoning



 “…[B]elief is more like a craftwork than a process of reasoning”—Madeline Bunting
First, Ms. Bunting strikes a feminist chord with the passage “belief is more like a craftwork than a process of reasoning.” Like Margaret Atwood, author of The Penelopiad (2005), she reconvenes belief within a woman centered worldview, gendering the notion of belief as craftwork. Consider the tale of the Odyssey and the absence of Odysseus from Penelope’s life: was her craftwork the evidence of her wit? If she succeeded in prolonging the advances of her suitors, so also belief prolongs, from this theological-anthropological view, a mode of fidelity in relationship, and it enacts an expression that communicates commitment in the midst of competing values.
a.       Primordial faith
Second, the metaphor of craftwork indicates the central dissatisfactions of what Dermot Lane calls “healthy secularization”. The metaphor indicates a resistance to propositional reasoning and the misgivings that have come with the decent of classical culture and prevailing winds, the flattening sense of history held in mainstream  culture, the needs for verified truth, the legitimacy given to the appeal to experience—however, all this has produced a “healthy secularization” (Lane 2003, 74). Craftwork is held in the Catholic Worker tradition as a mode of resistance to industrial era notions of machinery that have led to the commodification of time, and with capitalism, the exploitation of people. To invoke craftwork for belief, can therefore influence what Ormond Rush has called “hermeneutical reception” (Rush 2009, 74). That is, the wording allows for an alternative interpretation of the meaning of belief. It is only effective because of the existence of what Rahner has called the supernatural existential, or what Lane calls ‘primordial faith’. He defines this as “an attitude of trust and confidence and acceptance that is brought to bear on the value and worthwhileness of human existence” (Lane 2003, 76). The attitude of dissatisfaction with reasoning is also described by William James:
“your whole subconscious life, your impulses, your faiths, your needs, your devotions, have prepared the premises, of which your consciousness now feels the weight of the result; and something in you absolutely knows that result must be truer than any logic-copping rationalistic talk, however clever, that may contradict it’ (Brown 2004, 30).
In Lane’s terms the subconscious is ‘brought to bear’ on the meaning of existence. Just as important, the impulse of subconscious can contradict reason ‘however clever’. For her part, Ms. Bunting has contrasted the process of reasoning with craftwork to show that belief has bearing on human lives. The use of craftwork implicitly critiques the polarization of women’s lives from men’s lives and the false dichotomy wherefore women’s lives included craftwork at home, while rational men performed in public, as Odysseus did as war strategist while his ‘devotion’, Penelope, remained a domestic—the pair of his consciousness, thus his sub-consciousness. The reception of belief by women must be empowering of the “worthwhileness of [particularly their] existence” insofar as it acknowledges the surfeit of possibility in women that has for centuries been lost while belief defined as the process of reason categorically relegated women to secondary human existence.
b.      Yearning
Ms. Bunting is no exception in marking out belief in contrast to the process of reasoning. St. Augustine spoke of being impelled to belief: ‘without bodily force, he is drawn by a chain of his heart’ (“Confessions” Book 10, chapter 27). St. Aquinas pointed to an instinct of the heart (in affection) as how God drew one to belief (Lane 2003, 90). Likewise, Blaise Pascal distinguished from reason the ‘reasons of the heart’ (O’Collins 171). We certainly find belief represented biblically as attraction: “Jesus stayed out in the country; and people came to him from every quarter” (Mk 1:45). This attraction is a response to the “special revelation of the universal saving will of God in Christ” Lane writes, and the effect is “like a magnet drawing pieces of iron unto itself” (Lane 2003, 91). Thus, we come to belief, drawn by gentle force, as those who chose to visit with Jesus in the countryside to learn his teaching. Jesus is the Word of God, the ‘revelation that elicits faith’ (O’Collins 2011, 180). Like those who walked with Jesus we come to belief “…through the wisdom which gently draws the human … which leads it through visible realities to those which are invisible” (Gaudium et Spes n.15). Finally, belief is itself a “compelling conclusion” writes Gerard O’Collins, because in the same way we gradually came to know and love, then commit to a spouse, marriage gives further grounds to believe in that person (O’Collins 2011, 177). In other words, belief is not what one arrives at through an abstract, evidence-gathering procedure, but basically a personal engagement of the heart.
c.       Religious belief
The nature of craftwork raises a further vector of thought, namely, that it divests us of the pretentions of “pure” reason. In this case, belief tends in the direction of lived reality and the contention that we are “called to a real definitiveness” (Rahner and Weger 1981, 9). If craftwork means something, at least it connotes a humble work of beauty. Similarly, definitiveness means to act our choice where others can see it; if the world is a stage let the belief be known “in the full glare of the lights” (Rahner and Weger 1981, 16). This choice belies a contrast to primordial faith, what Dermot Lane distinguishes as religious faith. The definite religion is not a set of propositions but a medley, what John Henry Newman said of religion: “it is a rite, a creed, a philosophy, a rule of duty, all at once” (Brown 2004, 17). In this sense, belief is a craftwork to stitch together the meaning of our lives and something made not to linger in the mind but to be put forth before God and neighbor.

The so-called undogmatic Christianity



‘An undogmatic Christianity, one without the mediation of the church, would be a chimera’-International Theological Commission
While possible that the Spanish film director Luis Buñuel could have made a bilious character say such an expression in his film Nazarin, it seems obvious that many have experience of a kind of Catholicism hewn deep in culture which, in secular reflex, has made faith rarified. Rahner has acknowledged this and therefore harkened the magisterium to attend ‘the actual faith of the people’ thereby discovering ways in which official teaching is ‘already influenced from below’ (Rahner 1991, 172). In our view, what the ITC denounces as monstrous can be more properly understood as a confusion. At least four interpretations follow that indicate possible confusions one could have regarding church doctrine. Two deal with confusion about authority and two with confusion how doctrine mediates Jesus Christ. First, the proponent of an ‘undogmatic Christianity’ is likely to hold that doctrine interferes with the individual. For instance, conflict might mistakenly be assumed between the authority of conscience and authority of the magisterium. An offshoot of this is the concern of Latino theologian Orlando Espin that popular religion is dismissed as suspicion, ‘undogmatic’ when in fact it exists in reflection of “the culturally mediated character of all religious reception” (Gaillardetz 2002, 107). Second, one with this view can suggest antipathy toward ‘the teaching of the church’ and overlook the varying levels of authority held by different doctrine (Lennan 2004, 161). The flattening of such authority could be more properly understood as a way to name the center-periphery strategy often used blatantly unidirectionally (Gaillardetz 2002, 106). Third, apart from confusion with authority, is doctrine discontinuous with the historical Jesus or somehow divorced from the Gospels? The question could arise from a perceived dissonance from the Jesus Christ a believer knows and the one mediated in the church (Lennan 2004, 160). Fourth, more basically, an undogmatic Christianity would seem the project of someone convinced that doctrine itself fails to do its job. When it should aid the believer to know Jesus Christ and apprehend God’s will, it does just the opposite; for instance, through fault of language. Instead of elucidating the Truth of faith, the language obscures it with arcana and bigotry (Lennan 2004, 160). Taken together the preoccupations express a deeply held desire that faith be reasonable. Lacking in love, then indeed we might fear; still, we see Karl Rahner is right that the Spirit blesses the Church with unrest, fomenting opposition toward the forces of fossilization (Lennan 2004, 171). This desire is far from monstrous; though wild, it might even be tamed and led to see that a dogmatic Christianity is reasonable to support. Richard Gaillardetz has proposed a place for internal critique in the church, providing a model that giving a ‘fresh remembrance’ to the place of consensus fidelium (Gaillardetz 2002, 110). Participants can come into the church with dignity when shown that their end of consensus is vital (Gaillardetz 2002, 106).
             Pope Benedict XVI warns in the Regensburg address what we might call the thrust behind ‘undogmatic Christianity’ is a collapsed notion of reason which has intended to deHellenize Christianity for the sake of the so-called simple message of the New Testament. “[I]s the conviction that acting unreasonably contradicts God’s nature merely a Greek idea, or is it always an intrinsically true?” (Benedict XVI, Regensburg address, 3). With this inquiry, he confronts those who trumpet the primacy of conscience in a Kantian fashion where it is made into the internal magistrate of the good. This is the fallacy indicated by Timothy Radcliff, speaking of the “intolerance of those who believe that their words say it all” (Radcliffe 1996, 47). Purchased by the claim of a so-called “autonomous reason” the subject is decidedly cut off from the community. Imaginatively, what might this mean? Robert L. Wilken has depicted as “a map” what such reason rejects: “The Church’s way of speaking is a map of the experience of those who have known God” (Wilken 2006, 95). Johann Baptist Metz identified the perilous direction of a society wandering off alone, into an oblivion of self-understanding that will not cope another generation, i.e. in a future devoid of history and memory. To the credit of those who would ‘dehistoricize’ salvation history, society suffers one-dimensionality, a washed out ruling consciousness blank from the hopes as well as the terrors experienced in the past (Metz 2007, 182-83). We might therefore face a future where the atomic individualism of today has become a place of zero self-sacrifice, thus lacking Matthew 25, lacking what Rahner describes as the everyday interpersonal life established between love of God and love of neighbor (Rahner 1978, 456). In sum, without an interpersonal reason that sees ‘God as the horizon’, for whom is one self-realized?
To ameliorate such peril, Benedict XVI promotes “courage to engage the whole breadth of reason” (4-5). Such is the advantage of the Pope, presumed by Catholics to speak with authority on matters of faith and morals by means of inheriting the chair of St. Peter, and acting as the vicar of Christ, thus granted a supreme horizon on the ‘whole breadth of reason’. Ormond Rush adds a cautionary tale to the responsibilities of those who bear the teaching office. For instance, though not exhaustively limited to this one responsibility, the Pope is constrained in the exercise of reason “to safeguard and preserve the deposit of faith by making official judgments regarding its interpretations”(Rush 2009, 194).Not only for our good, but for future generations this task concerns the preservation of the faith, linked universally with what Rahner describes in ‘A Theology of Hope’:  “the will to guard and preserve is the basic virtue of life” (10, 258-59) It follows, since the teaching office is not limited exclusively to the Pope, theologians are  exhorted to interpret the deposit of faith, for example to interpret dogma in the light of ongoing tradition (Sullivan 1996, 115-16).

Saturday, December 15, 2012

Is the Parable of the Wedding Banquet (MT. 22:1-14) Contextual Theology? A Response to Metz


CR Spicer
14 December 2012
Dr. Richard Lennan
Foundational Theology
Boston College
 [open for revision]
“Fundamental theology seeks to explicate the faith in a manner corresponding to the present historical modes of human understanding. It does this, not in order to submit itself to the ruling modes of thought, but in order to enter into a fruitful conflict with these modes of thought.”—Johann Baptist Metz, Theology of the World, 82

IS THE PARABLE OF THE WEDDING BANQUET (MT. 22:1-14) CONTEXTUAL THEOLOGY?
A Response to Metz
For theology after Aushwitz the paradigm is not how to escape the river before the waterfall, but after falling, it is to brace ourselves for the impact we have coming.

I adjust this claim to contend that “the incarnation is continued” in contextual theology, drawing from Steven Bevans (‘Community as Source and Parameter of Theology, An Introduction to Theology in Global Perspective (Maryknoll NY: Orbis, 2009), 89-108) Johann Baptist Metz (‘On the Way to a Postidealist Theology’ A Passion For God: The Mystical-Political Dimension of Christianity (New York: Paulist, 1998) 30-53) Vincent Miller (‘The Body Globalized: Problems for a Sacramental Imagination in an Age of Global Commodity Chains” in Relgion, Economics, and Culture in Conflict and Conversation, ed. Laurie Cassidy & Maureen O’Connell (Maryknoll: Orbis, 2011), 108-20), Francis Schussler Fiorenza (‘The Cosmopolitanism of Roman Catholic Theology and the Challenge of Cultural Particularity’ Horizons 35/2 (2008):298-320) Karl Rahner (& Karl-Heing Weger Our Christian Faith: Answers for the Future. Tr. F. McDonagh (New York: Crossroad, 1981) 1-16), Robert Schreiter (‘Globalization and the Contexts of Theology, The New Catholicity: Theology Between the Global and the Local Maryknoll: Orbis, 1997), and Karen Teel (‘Christianity as Closed Monotheism? A contemporary Catholic Approach to Interreligious Dialogue’ in Religion, Economics, and Culture in Conflict and Conversation, ed. Laurie Cassidy & Maureen O’Connell (Maryknoll: Orbis, 2011), 255-75)

“Hope without faith would be blind. … It would tend to imagine the future looking like a mere repetition or copy of the present.”—Anthony Kelly, Eschatology and Hope, 17 (emphasis added)

We cannot forget who we are. The lacuna of our bodies in socio-economic location is named by Vincent Miller as the result of making no use of our phenomenological resources. With these we take up the sacramental work of the church and in effect “the incarnation is continued” (Miller 2011, 111). The choice before us is spelled out by German theologian Siegfried Widenhoffer: “to live in and from traditions, to have traditions, to criticize traditions, to abandon traditions, to create traditions, to let traditions grow or decline, to be committed to traditions, to hate traditions, etc--…to being a human being” because it is a false dilemma to live with or without what had ‘always been’ (Bevens 2009,  91, 105). To come back into our bodies means remembering the momentum our personal history has (though remembering our reliance on Greek thought would ground us too (Teel 2011, 266)) so that we draw up the inertial force of Christ with us who is our integral hope. If we are engaged in history, we soon know inserción requires the discourses of 1)liberation, 2)feminism, 3) ecology, and 4) human rights (Schreiter 1997, 16). When we draw upon Christ from the inertial Gospel of the poor we are a wire touching a surging outlet; we need conduction: Life touches us in contingency but community insulates us. On the contrary, fundamentalism: 1)the inerrancy of the Scriptures, 2) the virginal conception of Jesus, 3) substitionary atonement, 4) the bodily resurrection of Jesus, and 5)his bodily return in the Second Coming (Schreiter 1997,22) calculated the formal elements of faith, attempting a theocentric project. Yet ‘calculation never made a hero’ says Cardinal John Henry Newman…

            The Parable of the Wedding Banquet (Matthew 22:1-14)
Jesus replied: “The kingdom of heaven may be likened to a king who gave a wedding feast for his son…some ignored the invitation and…the rest laid hold of his servants, mistreated them, and killed them. The king was enraged…

…Heroic engagement with the world is our response to the force of Christ born within us in our “reflexive” being. Because “our subjectivity is achieved … in everyday life” (Miller 2011, 113) we are not “mere repetition” or copies of our self; for one moment erupts and up from within it emerges --our potential—another moment—“the ethnification that lives in changed social circumstances” (Schreiter 1997, 24), other shores  declare the Atantic Ocean the ‘Black Atlantic’ (Schreiter 1997, 16) and so on as the ground beneath our feet continues to be ‘deterritorialized’ (Schreiter 1997, 26). Elsewhere a ‘Fichtean’ approach prevails while here in the United States “the communitarian, particularist and pragmatic traditions have come to dominate” (Fiorenza 2008, 299). When incarnation is misplaced, this trend is made the problematic.
On the principle that hope is intelligible we cannot ground ourselves with nostalgia. Robert Schreiter is critical of a proposal by Archbishop Lefebvre to reissue Syllabus of Errors (Schreiter 1997, x). The bulk of the critique seems to be that the method of teaching in propositions is antiquated, yet Schreiter indicates that the aim of Lefebvre's proposal is to stear the Church back on course, a course derailed by Vatican II. On the one hand, the proposition method would reduce faith into a Rorschach ink-blot; on the other is the idea that issuing Syllabus of Errors 2.0 would deny the incarnation of Vatican II. At the very least, the proposal is evidence that in Catholic memory a Christendom remains fashioned imperial, imposing and stoic. Was the reality of Church ever so? Dogma is observed in nostalgia as ex-nihilo but we remember that “the dogma of Mary’s assumption was not made official until 1950, both the Eastern and Western church celebrated the feast for centuries” (Bevans 2009, 97). The anathemas of Vatican I were confirmed in the promises of Vatican II “so that there be no division” (1 Cor. 12:25). The true fault is to misplace the incarnation and on the one hand to create a painting titled ‘mother Dogma’ imagining mother church as the barren Sarah without child. The ‘one who laughed’ was born! On the other hand we misplace the incarnation when we create a painting titled ‘the Vision’ imagining church dogmas as the blindness of ten who could not see. Luke tells us Jesus asked, “Were not all ten cleansed?”

…The king was enraged…

What is the context in which the incarnation is left out? The direction of the question is important, (where are the other nine?), giving us ‘eyes to see’ to use Clovis Boff’s words (Brown 2004, 23), eyes necessary because this physique of obdurate formalism has resulted in piety that disinherited the poor and oppressed from the economy of salvation, e.g. the metaphor of Carl Schmitt’s political theology used by Fiorenza.  His  first sentence of Political Theology reads “The sovereign is the one who decides about the state of exception” (Fiorenza 2008, 310). This sovereign decides he is sui-generis, forgets his roots, leaves his parents to ‘cleave’ with power.
Historical reality is romantic: Our potential resists us but it cannot escape, and so on. But we leave out the incarnation if the reality of the United States Patriot Act has made us forget the internationalization of principles of human rights; a contextual theology must at least create the memorial.  Johann Baptist Metz says fundamental theology pursues the inevitable confrontation. “It seeks … corresponding to the present historical modes of human understanding” (Metz 82). It seeks… what? Modes of thought arrive (!) cataclysms of ‘it does this’ and then the ‘to me’ attaches; the grace: ‘it does this to me’ arriving redolent in reflective ‘ordering’, thus by grace we cannot forget who we are. David Tracy calls grace “a power erupting in one’s life as a gift revealing that Ultimate Reality can be trusted…” (Tracy 73). The incarnation is to be remembered. Explication begins here, delving his Santa Claus bag for gifts. He lets us correspond in history.
A second time he sent other servants, saying, ‘Tell those invited: “Behold, I have prepared my banquet…come to the feast.”
…Some ignored [them]…others took hold and mistreated them…

 “Can one ever really be indifferent to eternal life?” (Rahner and Weger 1981, 7).  To dwell on the cumbersome bonds that issue our arrest and captivate our being, for this, fundamental theology. To know that faith may intelligibly correspond in love and in history, for this, fundamental theology. Our integral hope means that even in suffering the categories give way; this is how fruitful conflict happens; birth by birth. We can forget that division of moments and separations do, finally, amount from longings we share deep down. If again the seam of reality parts way, ‘rise’ thusly: what for! How dare! Forget not such disturbances. Surely the tortured do not; David Hicks has not.[1] Allow despondence in momento mori when a record raises up a ghost. Our moment is after Guantánamo ; like Auschwitz “it cannot be ideationally explained and interpreted, but only remembered with a practical intent” (Metz 1998, 39). This way and inside this way (Jn 14:6), the moment-of-next-our-hope- is: realizing us. Merry Christmas! Professor Lennan.



[1] Coopes, Amy. “Australia drops Guantanamo memoirs case” Jul 24, 2012 http://www.google.com/hostednews/afp/article/ALeqM5gcFQMLqbV0h_oQOsvRUh8qUlXAuw?docId=CNG.7831f02b3a629db126c3145ea2acef7a.371 (accessed December 13, 2012).

The Historical Event Concetizes Conscience


C.R. Spicer
December 12, 2012
Dr. Andrea Vicini
Fundamental Moral Theology
Boston College
The Historical Event Concretizes Conscience
 “No one could have predicted that the match struck by Mohammed Bouazizi to set himself afire in Sidi Bouzid on December 17, 2010, would ignite the entire Arab world, but, the kindling had been laid  and was there for all to see years before… (Kenneth Pollack 2011, 3).
What are the implications of this understanding of conscience when we reflect on a concrete historical event (e.g. the Arab Spring)?
Contentions among differing notions of moral truth, reason and the nature of the self, under the light of this investigation, appear to resolve in definitions such as, conscience is “simply a dimension of the self” (Patrick 1996, 35). What may be missing is a fuller account of the way a historical event is self-constituting and the way that reason, the public reason through which we know ourselves, requires us to act truthfully in answer to questions about injustice. With Linda Hogan we argue that “in everyday choices the person concretizes her/his fundamental option” (Hogan 2001, 131). In short, the understanding of conscience is the activity of rectifying injustice, or we should like to remain alone before God, apophatic in spiritual life, taking the via negativa. Indeed, Iris Murdoch has called virtuous the search for our ‘unself’ (Murdoch 1970, 93). What we value as more unselfish is a self-in-relation. Within the world we stand “within” our conscience when we know our self-in-being-crucified. Historical events can sometimes fix us: “Hitherto shalt thou come, but no farther; here shall your proud waves be stayed” (Job 38.11).
By uncovering these contentions we invite moral theologians to de-mystify the conscience and explore the cataphatic implications of biblical, feminist and political perspectives. Thus, we defend the position that conscience is embodied sacred truth, that is irreducible to a politicized concept. It is sacred truth in the sense that conscience is divinely generated capacity that one has to receive sorrow in response especially to human brokenness. It is embodied in the sense that deeds matter and that the doer cannot escape from accountability not only before God but before neighbor. Giving emphasis on the embodiment of conscience recognizes the tension of faith that a socially conducted moral force within the human community is nevertheless indicative of God’s indwelling presence.
1.      Elements of Conscience: Moral Truth, Reason, Self
Which is moral truth—The plain and simple truth, the difficult truth, the honest truth—the descriptive or prescriptive, the subjective or objective—? Brian V. Johnstone notes that divergent notions or models of moral truth coincide within tradition. He is a proponent of a theology of tradition as ‘living tradition’, one that includes a plurality of positions in conflict but which must be in conflict in order for the tradition to be living (Johnstone 1995, 135). In one model, moral truth is defined as conformity between the conscience and the universal ‘nature of being’ or ontological order in the universe. This model has its root in an epistemology or theory of knowledge that was popularized in an era of moral guidelines or moral hand-manuals, hence the term manualists for the moral theologians of this period. Manualists from the 17th-19th centuries taught that truth was the conformity of the mind to objective reality. In this model, criterion of a true conscience is put in terms of obedience to God’s law: “the manuals of moral theology operated on a different epistemology… [where] conscience was conformity to the objective law and the moral order established by God” (Curran 2004, 19). Due to revisions of epistemology that the limits of this paper cannot discuss, this model of truth is held to be one among several.
In addition, Michael Himes identifies as part of the living tradition of the church: a) the model of moral truth as conformity of the conscience and rightly ordered striving and b) the further model of moral truth, as the conformity of conscience and the person’s whole spiritual relationship with God (Himes 2000, 133). A) Rightly ordered striving in moral life reflects the rise of virtue ethics. It means that the conscience serves in a person’s pursuit of the Good. The emphasis of the person marks one it apart from the first model which tended to focus on acts and therefore on the exercise of judgment by the conscience. B) Further, the third model likewise shifts from acts but this time reframes the ‘pursuit’ in terms of spirituality, thus drawing a broader circle around personhood. Situated in this model, the conscience can be viewed as the heart that discerns movements of the Holy Spirit with gifts from the Spirit.
Thus, a critical rudiment for discussion of the conscience is the notion of moral truth. Because God’s law and its application appeared to hold less importance in some theologians reflection on the conscience it was deemed necessary by the magisterium to observe the potential hazard. Pope John Paul II wrote in his encyclical Veritatis Splendor (1993) that moral theologians appear to propose a theory of ‘double truth’ (VS, 56). They have witnessed that an individual may act wrongly, and rightly; for an individual straitjacketed by limited material resources, for example, an act may be performed that is wrong in ‘itself’ but right. The Pope recognized a slippery slope argument: dramatically expressed by John Finnis: “the first socially approved exception to a norm, such as one may never choose to kill an innocent person, shows that there is no reason why we should limit satisfying our desires provided we are willing to accept the cost or risk” (Hogan 2001, 31) In effect, if some acts could be right in a given situation, what is the implication of situationally determined, moral activity, if not the diminishment of the value (God-) given to moral norms? The question critiques pluralism, supposes a worst-case scenario of subjectivism, yet preserves a consensus long held by shepherd Church, the truth, the way. Jurgen Moltmann  explains the Church’s concern for man: “When a man who cannot but be under the law arrogates to himself this exclusive right of a judge and puts himself in the judge’s place … he commits blasphemy of self-deification” (Moltmann 1974, 128-29).
We contend that the preservation of moral truth is still possible in one who exercises discernment of good means in given contexts. Further discussion on this point follows below where self-reification [making of one’s self a thing; e.g. “Conscience is a treasured commodity in contemporary culture” (Hogan 2001, 9)] is guarded against as the other extreme. Regarding the so-called ‘double’ of truth, the nearer question may ask about the model of moral truth in use by the theologian (VS, 56; cf. Johnstone 1995, 129). 
Reason
            Conscience is a judgment of reason (Catechism n. 1778). We can explore this teaching keeping in mind that prudence is either a) the right judgment of reason or b) analogous to art, we can gather a summary of the debate according to Johnstone:
“Some authors who favor an objective-intellectual model of conscience emphasize that conscience is distinct from prudence, and that conscience does not coincide with the act of prudence. Others, while insisting that prudence does not determine the truth of conscience, see the two as complementary, others again identify (right and certain ) conscience and prudence, or argue that prudence determines the truth of conscience” (Johnstone 1995, 133-34).
We should not be surprised that the multiple contentions appear to overlap with those of moral truth. Prudence is too human and therefore fallible to “determine” the truth of conscience. Non-determinists find fault with theories of the social-construction, which seem to deify man. To reason for the ‘creativity’ of conscience has risked such accusation for the purpose of vaulting the possibility of prudence, as virtue of conscience.
Reason must be open to the public, the everyman. It is a matter of who sets the agenda. At a basic level we would be remiss to forget that the driving option for the poor has indeed set the agenda for a discussion of reason. Background to support this opening follows.
The notion of reason has long invited the willing to ‘come and see’ (Jn. 1:39). Augustine held a neo-Platonic theory of illumination with which he articulated conscience, for the first time using the image of the voice of God (Demmer 2000, 17). Two paths diverged: on the one hand, in Thomas Aquinas’s emphasis of practical reasoning, prudence was analogous to art. With practice one obtained the deft ability to create from imagination what is appropriate, most expressive, yet keeping harmony among many parts (Curran 2004, 12). Speaking of imagination, Richard Gula points to the way we are shaped by magnanimous personalities, the superheroes of television and film, the Olympians—“such people fascinate us and hold more influence in our lives than abstract principles do” (Gula 1992, 97-98) On the other hand, William of Ockham (1285-1347) found that following the judgments of “right reason” qualified precedence to obedience to God’s will over the judgment of conscience because “in any given instance, one always has to admit at least the possibility of a change in the divine will” (Billy 2001, 7). From the period of medieval scholasticism through the era of the manualists, reason was depicted with increasing attention to rules and arguments were distilled by logical turns. Breaking from the company of his contemporaries, the manualist Zalba betrayed the legal model of conscience that had developed in view of syllogistic reasoning. Zalba pointed beyond the application of general principles in conscience to “a certain sense or intuition of probity” (Curran 2004, 8). Other notions of reason have been challenged. On the one hand, the Kantian view of the conscience as an internal tribunal reflected a reduction of reason to a subjective state of mind (Demmer 2000, 19). This subjectivism or autonomy of conscience is rejected in official Catholic teaching: “The assertion of a mistaken notion of autonomy of conscience…can be at the source of errors of judgment” (Catechism n. 1792).
On the other hand, the notion of a universal legislating reason strove for a kind of Archimedean standpoint situated beyond historical and cultural contingency (Benhabib 1992, 3). In what is accepted as the underpinning proposal for Linda Hogan’s work on conscience (Hogan 2001, 130), Seyla Benhabib has more recently built a case for a move “from a substantialistic concept of rationality to a discursive, communicative concept” (Benhabib 1992, 5). She is skeptical that a universalist legistlating [sic] reason could deal with situation and context “with which practical reason is always confronted (Benhabib 1992, 3). Due to its genderblindness, legistlating reason has failed to give the condition for “thematization” of issues most important for women (Benhabib 1992, 13). She argues for what she calls “a Habermasian model of the public sphere” where what is reasonable to discuss “cannot be limited a priori” and further, “lines can be redrawn by the participants in the conversation” (Benhabib 1992, 13). With the cultivation of “representative thinking”—a term she borrows from Hannah Arendt—she asserts that “universalism is still viable: if interactive, cognizant of gender difference, contextually sensitive, and not situation indifferent” (Benhabib 1992, 3, 8). Using these proposals, Linda Hogan has put forward a personalist model which emphasizes autonomy of the person and prioritizes responsibility of individuals in moral matters. Further, conscience mediates the divine law; and ethics must give recognition to the role of circumstances and intentionality (Hogan 2001, 29). According to Brian Johnstone there is an “element of a personalist understanding of conscience in GS [Gaudium et Spes n. 16], also present in Vertitatis Splendor” (Johnstone 1995, 134).


Self
A third component necessary for a discussion of conscience is the notion of the self. The Second Vatican Council referred to above was the first document in Church history to provide official teaching about the conscience. The passage above cited on the ‘dignity of conscience’ allows for theological investigation, both regarding language of personal dignity as well as an interpretation of conscience that is personalist, i.e. “not in relation to an abstract, ontological order, but in regard to the ontology of the person” (Johnstone 1995, 134-35). “In reality persons are constituted in a complex unity of fragmentary and varying narratives, commitments and values that change over time and that may pull us in different directions” (Hogan 2001, 129)
In classical antiquity it was popular to refer to an individual’s experience of awareness or consciousness. For the philosopher Chrysippus this was not exclusive to humans and therefore indicated animal life; he included no moral element but simply a consciousness that a creature has “of its own composition” (Pierce 1955, 14). Compare this to the Lacanian view in psychoanalysis in what he calls the “mirror stage of development” (Lacan 1996, 334). Judith Butler states in Bodies that Matter that in this view an identification made with another precedes the ego; that this continues into adulthood where identificatory relations “are never simply made or achieved; they are insistently constituted, contested, and negotiated” (Butler 1993, 76). She took a Nietzscean tact to emphatically claim there was no doer behind the deed in order to stress that gender was strictly something performative (Butler 1990: 25). Seyla Benhabib is likewise skeptical of the “male” ego that is “abstract, disembedded, autonomous” (Benhabib 1992, 3). In her view, others must be viewed as concrete others but she qualified this: “view every moral person as a unique individual, with a certain life history, disposition and endowment, as well as needs and limitations” (Benhabib 1992, 10). For Sidney Callahan, “[t]here must be an awareness or connectedness with the real outer environment at the same time as an awareness of the inner environment of the self as self” (Callahan, 2001 41). This indicates an operation in a “complex double-directed way” (Vischer 2010, 10). According to Anne Patrick: “the individual is always a self-in-relation to others, and our awareness of moral obligation is intimately bound up with our experiences of others who are significant in our lives” (Patrick 1996, 36). Further explorations at the crossroads of gender study and theology show that new readings of Biblical texts are possible when the self is reconceived as a self-in-relation (Tamez 2012, 84; Wacker 2012, 70).
2.      Re-defining Conscience
Conscience is embodied sacred truth…I concretize conscience to emphasize its potency in the world following Bultmann: “What man has done and does—his decisions—constitute him in his true nature, that he is essentially a temporal being” (Hauerwas 1994, 147). Embodiment of moral agency will come to mean in Linda Hogan’s words ‘confronting the truth’ (Hogan 2001). To understand the technology-power of the individual, we pause over Michel Foucault’s apocalyptic Politics of Truth p.181
“techniques which permit individuals to perform, by their own means, a certain number of operations on their own bodies, on their own souls, on their own thoughts, on their own conduct, and this in such a way that they transform themselves, modify themselves, and reach a certain state of perfection, of happiness, of purity, of supernatural power, and so on.” (Holland 2002, 81)
The passage relates how one can form an alliance with oneself to overcome conditions; however, he challenges once more with the notion of truth which at the extreme is called self-deification. Josef Fuchs has similarly established a domain of inner harmony within the self wherein the alliance with self can transcend oneself. He builds on the fundamental option or deepest core choice of being in relationship with God; again, the ever present awareness one has of herself and therefore says ‘yes’ toward a welcome embrace already prepared, such is the consciousness of oneself created and therefore deeply recognizing the ever-Creator God (Fuchs 1987, 122). The hallowed events of prayer appear to occur in this inner chamber or what he terms, “the subject-oriented dimension of conscience” (Fuchs 1987, 124). We think it is from this profound connection that one can source resilience to overcome oppression, e.g. solitary confinement.
In his classic Discipline and Punish Foucault perceives how the ideal prison is structured to maximize supervision of inmates while minimizing the expense to society. His analysis of Jeremy Bentham’s ideal prison or Panopticon illustrates a central observation tower where all inmates are visible, while the inmate at no time is aware whether or not he is observed. Some external indications that he is watched are enough to give the inmate the impression that he is watched in perpetuity and thereafter, whether or not a guard is present in the tower the inmate monitors his own behavior according to what will serve his self-interest, namely avoid further penalty. As Judith Butler notes this is an attempt to appropriate the Nietzschen concept of internalization (Butler 1990, 29).
The notion of the self that we use here identifies the sociological plane of the person to be explicit about the structural violence one experiences in solitary confinement. Some further comments on the self can clarify the “sight” of the psychological wound made by this punishment. Butler’s work Gender Trouble is a critique of the notion of the disembedded, autonomous self. Her project recruits from Nietzche in denying being, quoting On the Genealogy of Morals: “there is no doer behind the deed” in her argument that gender is purely performative (Butler 1990, 25). According to Paula Black, who surveys a feminine culture, another who has taken the Foucauldian view is Sandra Lee Bartky. She asserts that women internalize the so called “Beauty-Complex” in order to avoid the internal and external sanctions for non-conformity (Black 2006, 145-49). The internal sanctions are expressed by Charles Taylor’s analysis of the identity crisis: “I define who I am by defining where I speak from, in the family tree, in social space, in the geography of social statuses and functions, in my intimate relations to the ones I love, and also crucially in the space of moral and spiritual orientation within which my most important defining relations are lived out” (Taylor 1989, 35). When these same important defining relations are unable to be lived out, a crucial dimension of oneself is imperil.  
On the contrary, the pursuit of a concretized fundamental option involves the restructuring of oneself through bonds of love and solidarity. We can renegotiate our identity so that our own well-being depends on the well-being of those who face crushing burdens.
Patrick: “Internalizing the voices of the victims of injustice … This may in fact be … that elusive entity we call a ‘properly formed conscience’—one that hears the voices of those adversely affected by the systems we live by, as well as by what we choose to do and what we never get around to doing” (Patrick 1996, 197)

The Historical Perspective of the ‘Primacy of Conscience’
Here we revisit the terrain of ambiguity mentioned in the discussion of moral truth. We stated earlier that some theologians “have witnessed that an individual may act wrongly, and rightly; for an individual straitjacketed by limited material resources, for example, an act may be performed that is wrong in ‘itself’ but right.” We consider a historical overture beginning with the contributions to the theology of conscience from Bernard of Clairvaux, Peter Abelard (Keenan 2010, 39). These contemporaries dealt with the confusion of values one can make and therefore the wrongness of actions one can take--hence the phenomena of “erroneous conscience”. Clairvaux (1090-1153) taught that all falsehood was sinful but not Abelard (1079-1142), who opined of moral motives. The lie that protects the safety of oneself or another is not a sin; in fact just the opposite, and we should not be called sinners for this, but be known as truly good.
Enter Peter Lombard (1095-1160). Must one obey church teaching? The presumption is heavily affirmative. That the teaching of the church should always be held sacred was only questionable to the extent there was a rising affirmation that the conscience held authority. Lombard ( may have posed the dilemma provocatively; and then hedged, “affirming that one is not obliged to follow one’s conscience when at odds with church teaching” (Keenan 2010, 36). Aquinas crested the rising wave that the conscience held ultimate authority. From Aquinas we hold in tradition the ‘primacy of conscience’.
Fast forward to the Second Vatican Council and we see these two strains in The Declaration of Religious Liberty . n.14 resembles the position of Lombard: “in forming their consciences the faithful must pay careful attention to the holy and certain teaching of the church. For the Catholic Church is by the will of Christ the teacher of truth.” In short, the Church holds authority. On the other hand,  n.3 resembles the position of Aquinas: “The human person sees and recognizes the demands of the divine law through conscience. All are bound to follow their conscience faithfully in every sphere of activity so that they may come to God, who is their last end.”
The Catechism of the Catholic Church published by John Paul II (1993, 1997) appears unambiguous between these two positions. We see that “education of conscience is indispensable” (n. 1783) that it is “a lifelong task” (n. 1784) and are reminded that “conscience can make an erroneous judgment” (n. 1786). Thus the Catechism gives emphasis to the position of Lombard.
Biblical Perspective: Consequent Conscience
We follow the careful reading of St. Paul in the context of Hellenist culture by C.A. Pierce, a protestant theologian and author of The Conscience in the New Testament (1955).  
Because we are approaching the topic of conscience from a starting point of the Arab Spring and therefore the inflicted awareness of structures of sin that the popular uprisings brought to worldwide attention, it is appropriate to assume the presuppositions that are more typical of Protestant scholars, that is, coming to Scripture with a heightened sense of sin and the notion of salvation by a God who saves, even if later we will resume the Catholic stress on works and their importance in God’s plan. It is well accepted that St. Paul uses the word syneidesis  ( συνεδησις) which he found from popular Hellenist usage (Curran 2004, 6). Philipe Delhaye has defined syneidesis as “the moral personality, the centre of the soul where choices are worked out and responsibilities undertaken” (Delhaye 1968, 42).  Such a definition for conscience is for C.A. Pierce unacceptable if it understands choice with orientation toward the future: “Conscience is the reaction of the whole man to his own wrong acts. … Conscience does not look to the future (Pierce 113, 114)” Moreover, “The New Testament emphatically denies the view that regards conscience as a guide to future action” (Pierce 1955, 117).
Catholic writers such as Claus Demmer are quick to point out that conscience is no way an oracle, but more like an organ that functions in the human person in service of one’s being in Christ. The reliance here is not in fact on the Greek syneidesis but the term introduced by Jerome in his translation to Latin—synderesis—which Demmer says “describes the power of conscience that survived even the Fall and was understood as the person’s inner call to authenticity and pursuit of the human good” (Demmer 2000, 17). In this view synderesis refers to a person’s faculty of apprehension (Vischer 2010, 3). The Catholic Catechism proclaims: “when he listens to his conscience, the prudent man can hear God speaking” (n. 1777). The ‘voice of God’ metaphor is better understood as a neo-Platonic concept as formulated by St. Augustine:
Augustine is particularly [influential] …he associated for the first time the reality of conscience with the image of the voice of God. To understand this image, one must view it not as an infallible oracle but, against the backdrop of the “theory of illumination,” as a neo-Platonic theory that Augustine reinterpreted according to his theology of creation and his epistemology. It is perfectly clear, then, why conscience is defined as sedes Dei—that is, the privileged place in the person where God dwells. (Demmer 17)
What Demmer alludes to finally, of course, is paragraph 16 of Gaudium et Spes, from the Second Vatican Council:Conscience is the most secret core and sanctuary of a person. There we are alone with God, Whose voice echoes in our depths (John 1:3, 14).” Catholic tradition is highly positive: “In a wonderful manner conscience reveals that law which is fulfilled by love of God and neighbor” (GS 16; cf. Eph. 1:10). This official teaching is the basis for theologians to argue: “…just as the conscience of Antigone, [the conscience] can recognize a higher claim that exposes the pretensions of tyranny and oppressive social conventions.” Yet it must be remembered that the Greek syneidesis carried from Hellenistic usage a far different meaning. I suggest that the meaning is in defense of the oppressed, for as Monsignor Romero of El Salvador said, “let those who have a voice, speak out for the voiceless”. Our God has given us a voice; silence is the voice of complicity (Bourgeois 24).
C.A. Pierce might point to the phrase in Gaudium et Spes “to obey [the conscience] is the very dignity of being human; according to it we will be judged” (GS 16; 2 Cor. 6:10). For Pierce, a Hellenist reading of this would have a very ominous sound. To reach this conclusion he studied Stobaeus who tracks popular phrases from the sixth, fifth and fourth centuries BC and first century AD. Syneidesis belonged to a group of popular phrases taken up as material by Ethics. A related term αύτᾧ συνειδέναι is the focus of Pierce’s study: “[It] means literally I am conscious of…in myself or I feel that I…. A use of this developed from this where the content of the consciousness is the moral quality of the subject’s own acts or behavior” He points to how Euripides (440 BC) makes Orestes say he suffers syneidesis (συνεδησις): he knows that he has done terrible things (Pierce 30). Inclusion of the moral element of αύτᾧ συνειδέναι Pierce defines it: “to share knowledge with one’s self—to be privy…with one’s self—to hug a (possibly guilty) secret to one’s self—to be a witness for or against one’s self or to bear witness to one’s self” (Pierce 18). The ominous sound reverberates again as Socrates is condemned to die on false testimony; “he is content to let their own συνεδησις punish those who perjured against him” (Pierce 1955, 40).  Philo (40 AD) calls it the terrible accuser, the judge and witness; Plutarch (80 AD) called it an ulcer in the flesh; pain; suffering parallel with the memory of ill deeds (Pierce 140-141). Such woe is like a gambler cursed forever with “the worse lot” (Wisdom 17.11). This recounting is necessary since the New Testament writers had no material inspiration from the Old Testament (Pierce 1955, 13). He summarizes:
Συνεδησις comes into Christianity entirely from the everyday speech of the ordinary Greek with its own connotation, basically, the pain suffered by man, as man, and therefore as a creature involved in the order of things, when, by his acts complete or initiated, he transgresses the moral limits of his nature (Pierce 1955, 54)
Nothing indicates that the meaning of synderesis had to do with the future. The manner of expression to the one Paul will use (αύτᾧ συνειδέναι) is in Xenophon used as a moral positively good: “We know with ourselves that we began as children and still continue in the practice of noble and good works” (Pierce 1955, 23).  For Paul it is “I am not conscious of anything against me…but the one who judges me is…” (1 Cor 4.4). Even if softened by St. Paul the connotation of terror is implied in his awe of the Lord. What we turn to next will show that the terror is always rooted in reality, because actions that do not conform to conscience mean the future destruction of community.
Revisiting Truth: The Notion of Truth in a U.S. Context
Observations made above revealing contentions about models of truth can now be revisited. In general the philosophic contention of truth is mixed with a socio-cultural one. The Greek Philosopher Diogenes pronounced that he could walk the earth in search of one honest man, and it was said that the American Experiment would produce the environment that honest man could live in.
We saw that Michael Himes points to models of truth expressed by the conscience in right striving and as reflective of one’s spiritual relationship with God. For example, one assumes God is with us and to probe forward, can always asking oneself on the brink of decision, “By acting this way, do I bring myself closer to God?” (Delhaye 1968, 246). Himes, theology professor at Boston College and author of Doing the Truth in Love (1995), speaks of truth at what could be one of the epi-centers of American virtue ethics, a theological outgrowth of post-Vatican II. To disregard the climate of national election as a secular sphere from which the human personality read the signs of the times is in such a view to dissemble the human in abstracto. It must be admitted then that in the context of my study at Boston College there is a certain gravity that motivates the question.
 Contextual theologies consider the relevance of an author writing in situ where, by convenience of cultural proximity, one’s access to sensus fidelium or the sense of the faithful stipulates the conditions of his reception of Catholic tradition. We have in mind the work of James Cone (‘Jesus is Black’) Rosemary Radford Ruether (Woman Healing the Earth) or Clemens Sedmak (Doing Local Theology). The implications for the character of an individual have been traced by Stanley Hauerwas. He takes into account the charge against striving-man: Sisyphus-like, in the words of Moltmann: “suffering in a superficial, activist, apathetic and therefore dehumanized society can be a sign of spiritual health” (Moltmann 315). Hauerwas distinguishes “contextualism” from “situationalism” where the former means that the Christian life is determined by conforming to what ‘God is doing in the world to make and keep human life human’ and the later allows the self to be at the mercy of each new event “as if it must constantly begin anew” yet this maintains the guard of God’s free grace (Hauerwas 1994, 5, 6). Philipe Delhaye: “Choice after choice, he builds his ‘self’; he fashions for good or ill his moral interior: intus hominis quod conscientia vocatur (Augustine, In Ps., 45,3, PL 36, 515 C)” (Delhaye 1968, 97). St. Augustine famously framed the balance of contemplation and action on the tension of Mary and Martha, Peter and John. These moral pairs indicate the inward-outward dynamism of one’s spiritual relationship with God, and consequently the context-spirit-context rhythm of one’s worldly circulation. Further, the pairs should suggest the intersubjectivity that, Richard McCormick says determines the objective moral quality of our actions:
The morality of our actions requires a larger setting than that present in the assessment of immediate effects—that of community-building or destruction of community. Every action, as an intersubjective reality, is either a form of community or destruction of it. That determines its objective moral quality” (McCormick 1978, 14).
            In sum, we return to the search of Diogenes for the honest man. Honesty requires more than telling a truth. It means more than eternal repetition of that truth. To speak the truth is never enough. Truth is chosen in community where it bears likeness; honesty is to act with integrity in the world. Communities are built one act of conscience at a time, constantly building itself anew.

Toward a Politicized Conscience
Is the conscience a politicized concept? How have some appropriated the Catholic Moral discourse on conscience in the public arena? Various prominent U.S. Catholics publicly dissented with papal teaching of Humanae Vitae on account of conscience (Patrick 1996, 102-33). More recently, truth claims made on the authority of conscience have arisen in discussions among U.S. Catholics concerning the cases of prominent scholars Margaret Farley and Elizabeth Johnson in addition to the well-known activist Roy Bourgeois. Oppositional editorializing among U.S. Catholics evidently existed when Josef Fuchs felt impelled to erase the error:
“The dilemma ‘conscience or magisterium’ …does not exist. There exists only living fidelity in the church as the hierarchically ordered community, but this in turn cannot exist without the responsible conscience of those who bear the fidelity, for it is only via the responsibly formed conscience that the magisterium can achieve significance in the life of the person.’ (Fuchs 1993, 165)
The operative word that Fuchs uses is fidelity. He claims to negotiate tension between teaching and practice in terms redolent with the connotation of committed relationship. For example, the American Jesuit John Courtney Murray is remembered for the cosmopolitanism advanced carefully in the Declaration on Religious Freedom, produced during the Second Vatican Council.  In a prime example where nuance protected the capacity for individual Catholics to make authoritative claims of conscience we see room allowed for guidance to come not strictly from the magisterium but also from more proximate authorities. Paragraph n. 14 states, “In the formation of their consciences, the Christian faithful ought carefully to attend to the sacred and certain doctrine of the church.” As Richard Gula notes, a previous draft read “Ought to form their consciences according to the teaching of the church” (Gula 1989, 159). Because the Bishops declared this too restrictive replacing “according to” with the less compulsory “attend to” Gula finds that the church has not made its own teaching the exclusive source for moral discernment. “The less restrictive reading means … Other circumstantial and personal factors also must be considered in trying to resolve a conflict of values.” (Gula 1989, 159)

The Truth of Mohammed Bouazizi and the Arab Spring
The United Nations’ Arab Human Development Report in 2003 shows the recommendations for emergency repairs to meet the projected needs to support a bulging population of youth (Pollack 2011, 3). Nonconformity with these recommendations is one factor producing instability in the North African/Near East regions. The culpability of any single individual has not been questioned, nor has the UN body been faulted.
Let us now address the phenomena of Arab Spring while recalling our initial foray into contentions with moral truth, reason, and self. For failure to implement the UN recommendations, one might say, moral truth was not obtained. That is not obvious if we use the first model of truth in a syllogistic sense. Recall this that this model addresses the conformity of the conscience to God’s law. Murder is against the commandment of God; the man murdered himself so it must be a wrongful act. Here one’s self is reduced to his doing; and while we agree that the moral man must be performative, and that intentions to repair injustice are insufficient, in this sense the deed is everything. But one’s self is in fact symbolic, a performance of relationality, and this means the being counts. We must be held accountable!
Moral truth is also found recognizing that the UN recommendations require persons to implement them. We ask who is the doer behind the deed? Thus, if we consider the intelligence of Mohammed Bouazizi to emulate the famous self-immolation by a Vietnamese Buddhist monk whose blazing image touched the moral imagination of a guilty, imperial nation, then we begin to use the second model in assessment of the rightly ordered striving. This model of moral truth shows concern for the person in the midst of circumstances and how the person strives virtuously to flourish. In this view it is possible to see the significance of Qatar’s Academy of Change which was responsible for enhancing the capacity for change by promoting the work of non-violent theorist Gene Sharp’s From Dictatorship to Democracy (Christiansen 2012, 133). The view of the person as a socially constituted being takes account how Bouazizi became inseparable from activists in Tahrir Square and acknowledges the process by which the eventual judgment of revolution was prepared, what practical reasoning and strategies from Sharp were appropriated to the Egyptian context. Oppressive tactics by the government deterred such organizing, so in this view of moral truth the question of the non-deterministic psychologist Sidney Callahan has special place: “How does a person develop and maintain an adherence to conscience in the face of intense deprivation, psychological pressure, persecution, and outright torture?” (Callahan 1991, 4).
Again, to use the third model recall that Himes suggested that conformity of the conscience and the whole spirituality of a person. Unlike the first model in which awareness to principles and norms is stressed, this model includes the value of moral emotions and everyday moral interactions in our micro-relationships (friends, family, co-workers) and in our macro-relationships (international relations). If the first model should emphasize the corporal works of mercy, and the second call for the virtue of solidarity, the third attributes the sin of sloth to neglect of furtherance of the common good. If we presume in our view the Catholic Papal Social Teaching against social sin then we could view how the recommendations pointed to flaws in the societal structure of education and industry for which policy and programs would require immediate injection of capital as well as legislative infrastructure, capacity building for implementation and enforcement; the recommendations signified a moral claim in the sense that structural poverty is scientifically proven to create conditions of disease and crime, while preventing access to nutrition, health care, education and skilled employment. Since it was given appropriate recommendations to restructure, the neglect of such reform led to an intolerable grievance of people as they came to recognize the choices that their government had made. A proponent of the first model might take into account Catholic Papal Social Teaching qualifying with growing favor the means of non-violence to resist the aggression of an armed oppressor[1]. More likely however, without recognition of the intention of the person or the spirituality of moral coercion it is doubtful that the selected moral norm to apply would be the honor of one’s parents or the love of neighbor because of the baldness of the suicide.

Epilogue
We find that historical events confront us. Conscience takes into account the concrete historical event bearing moral claims that we halt. We respond “within” conscience when signs of injustice have a way of implicating us in our personal lives. “Conscience is the subsequent pain which indicates that sin has been committed by the man who suffers it.” (Pierce 1955, 117). The reality of the world is in fact not remote, nor God remote to the reality of the world. Conscience is what inflicts one with the sorrows of the world; not ‘God-in man’ but ‘the pain suffered by man’ (Pierce 1955, 54) e.g. the cry of the poor. The gift of remorse stings us in conscience; this is not ‘truth in itself’ but ‘truth in myself’(Fuchs 1987, 125). It stings so that we acknowledge our failing for not having more deeply committed to God’s justice. Conscience can be the place at the foot of the cross where we gain a felt-sense of shared suffering with crucified peoples. The consequent conscience, ultimately, is where we recognize our self-in-being-crucified.
Emphasis on the model of moral truth where conscience is in conformity to the whole spirituality of a person raises other implications. Much of spirituality specifies what in giving emphasis on the inflicting, consequent conscience we have not. We know with Aquinas that prudence is an art, and we know the practice required to discern the spirits that come to the soul. The different inspirations sift out into peace or remorse, for “especially in considering the consequent conscience, the remorse of a bad conscience is contrasted with the peace of a good conscience” (Curran 2004, 10). It was the proposal of ours that reflection on a concrete historical event led us to immediate conclusions about reality and that we had to rectify injustice rather than perpetuate it. What follows could allow the sequel, showing what the antecedent conscience means and exploring the fullness of analogical implications: where conscience is to person, the Arab Spring is to Global Civil Society. These three starting points head in that direction.
1.      Is Bouazizi one of ‘those who renounce the use of violence…and resort to methods of defence that are otherwise available to weaker parties’ ? Gaudium et spes (n. 78)

2.      Is the Arab Spring a sign of the Holy Spirit? “Among the signs of hope we should also count the spread…of a new sensitivity ever more opposed to war as an instrument of resolution of conflicts between peoples, and increasingly oriented to find effective but ‘non-violent’ means to counter the armed aggressor” (John Paul II 1995, 27).

3.      “It is undeniable that the goals that inspire the movements (Human dignity, self-government, the rule of law, non-violent political change, and sometimes religious pluralism) are also the aspirations which recent Catholic Social Teaching has identified as signs of the times.” (Christiansen  2012, 133-34).




Bibliography
Augustine through the Ages : An Encyclopedia 1999., edited by Allan Fitzgerald, John C. Cavadini. Grand Rapids, Mich.: William B. Eerdmans Pub.
Catechism of the Catholic Church 1994., edited by Catholic Church. Liguori, MO: Liguori Publications.
"Catholic Conscience : Foundation and Formation : Proceedings of the Tenth Bishops' Workshop, Dallas, Texas." 1992. In , edited by Russell E. (Russell Edward) Smith and Pope John XXIII Medical-Moral Research and Education Center, 7-112. Braintree, Mass.: Pope John Center.
Charity in Truth = Caritas in Veritate : Encyclical Letter 2009., edited by X. V. Benedict. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.
The Christian Social Conscience / by a Group of Laymen 1965. London: G. Chapman.
Conscience 2004., edited by Charles E. Curran. New York: Paulist Press.
Ecofeminism and the Sacred 1993., edited by Carol J. Adams. New York: Continuum.
"Gene Sharp Navigator." 2011.New York Times, February 17, 2011.
Spirituality and Moral Theology : Essays from a Pastoral Perspective 2000., edited by James Keating. New York: Paulist Press.
The Splendor of Truth = Veritatis Splendor : Encyclical Letter, August 6, 1993 1993. Washington, D.C.: United States Catholic Conference.
Women Healing Earth : Third World Women on Ecology, Feminism, and Religion 1996., edited by Rosemary Radford Ruether. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books.
Benedict XVI, Pope, 1927-. 2007. On Conscience : Two Essays. Philadelphia : San Francisco: National Catholic Bioethics Center.
Benhabib, Seyla. 1992. Situating the Self : Gender, Community, and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. New York: Routledge.
Berger, Barbara. 1996. "A Sense of Orders: An Introduction to the Theory of Jacques Lacan." In Narration and Therapeutic Action: The Construction of Meaning in Psychoanalytic Social Work, edited by Jerrold R. Brandell, 83-98. New York: Haworth Press.
Billy, Dennis Joseph. 2001. "Conscience and Prayer : The Spirit of Moral Theology." In , edited by James Keating, 1-24. Collegeville, Minn.: Liturgical Press.
Black, Paula. 2006. "Discipline and Pleasure." In Feminism in Popular Culture, edited by Joanne Hollows and Rachel Moseley. New York: Berg Press.
Bourgeois, Roy. 2012. My Journey from Silence to Solidarity. Yellow Springs, Ohio: fxBear.
Braidotti, Rosi. 1987. "The Politics of Radical Immanence: May 1968 as an Event; New Formations." New Formations 65 (1): 10 October 2012.
Braidotti, Rosi. 1994. Nomadic Subjects : Embodiment and Sexual Difference in Contemporary Feminist Theory. New York: Columbia University Press.
Budziszewski, J., 1952-. 2003. "What we can't Not Know : A Guide." In , 203. Dallas, Tex.: Spence Pub. Co.
Burke, Kevin F. 2000. The Ground Beneath the Cross : The Theology of Ignacio Ellacuría. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
Butler, Judith. 1993. Bodies that Matter. New York: Routledge.
Butler, Judith P. 1990. Gender Trouble : Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York: Routledge.
Cahill, Lisa Sowle. 1996. "The Bible and Christian Moral Practices." In Christian Ethics : Problems and Prospects, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and James F. Childress, 3-17. Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.
Callahan, Sidney Cornelia. 1991. In Good Conscience : Reason and Emotion in Moral Decision Making. San Francisco: Harper.
Christiansen, Drew. 2012. "The Arab Spring: Muslim Non-Violence as a Sighn of the Times." In Gender in Theology, Spirituality and Practice, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and Diego Irarrázaval. Vol. 4. London: SCM Press.
Cone, James. 1998. "God is Black." In Lift Every Voice: Constructing Christian Theologies from the Underside, edited by Susan Brooks Thistlethwaite and Mary Potter Engel, 101-14. Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis Books.
Conn, Walter E. 1980. Conscience--Development and Self-Transcendence. Birmingham, Ala.: Religious Education Press.
Darwin, Charles, 1809-1882. 1952. The Origin of Species : By Means of Natural Selection; the Descent of Man : And Selection in Relation to Sex. Chicago: Encyclopædia Britannica.
Delhaye, Philippe. 1968. The Christian Conscience. New York: Desclee Co.
Demmer, Klaus, 1931-. 2010. Living the Truth : A Theory of Action. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
———. 2000. Shaping the Moral Life : An Approach to Moral Theology, edited by James F. Keenan. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
Farley, Margaret A. 1996. "The Role of Experience in Moral Discernment." In Christian Ethics : Problems and Prospects, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and James F. Childress, 134-151. Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and Punish : The Birth of the Prison. New York: Pantheon Books.
Fuchs, Josef, 1912-. 1987. "Christian Morality : The Word Becomes Flesh." In , 119-42. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
———. 1993. "Moral Demands and Personal Obligations." In . Translated by Brian McNeil, 153-70. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
Ghonim, Wael, 1980-. 2012. Revolution 2.0. London: Fourth Estate.
Godman, Peter. 2009. Paradoxes of Conscience in the High Middle Ages : Abelard, Heloise, and the Archpoet. Cambridge, UK ; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Grisez, Germain Gabriel, 1929-. 1983. "The Way of the Lord Jesus." In . Vol. 1, 661-82, 871-98. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press.
Gula, Richard M. 1989. Reason Informed by Faith : Foundations of Christian Morality. New York: Paulist Press.
Gustafson, James M. 1994. A Sense of the Divine : The Natural Environment from a Theocentric Perspective. Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.
Harrington, Daniel J. 2010. Paul and Virtue Ethics : Building Bridges between New Testament Studies and Moral Theology, edited by James F. Keenan. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield.
Hauerwas, Stanley, 1940-. 1994. Character and the Christian Life : A Study in Theological Ethics. Notre Dame Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.
Himes, Kenneth R. 2000. "Formation of Conscience: The Sin of Sloth and the Significance of Spirituality." In . New York: Paulist Press.
Hinze, Bradford E. and Christine Firer Hinze. 2012. "The Elizabeth A. Johnson Case in the United States." In Gender in Theology, Spirituality and Practice. Vol. 4. London: SCM Press.
Hogan, Linda, 1964-. 2001. "Confronting the Truth : Conscience in the Catholic Tradition." In , 1-35, 127-64. London: Darton, Longman and Todd.
Hollanbach, David. 1996. "Tradition, Historicity, and Truth in Theological Ethics." In Christian Ethics : Problems and Prospects, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and James F. Childress, 60-75. Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.
Holland, Nancy J. 2002. ""Truth as Force": Michel Foucault on Religion, State Power, and the Law." Journal of Law and Religion 18 (1): 79-97.
Johnstone, Brian V. 1995. "Erroneous Conscience in Veritatis Splendor and the Theological Tradition." In , edited by Selling, John A. & Jans,Jan. Grand Rapids, Michigan: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.
Keenan, James F. 2010. Moral Wisdom : Lessons and Texts from the Catholic Tradition. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Khalil, Ashraf. 2011. Liberation Square : Inside the Egyptian Revolution and the Rebirth of a Nation. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Lacan, Jacques, ed. 1996. The Mirror Stage as Formative of the FUnction of the I as Revealed in Psychoanalytic Experience. The Continental Philosophy Reader, edited by Richard Kearney andMara Rainwater. London ; New York: Routledge.
McCormick, Richard. 1978. "Ambiguity in Moral Choice." In Doing Evil to Achieve Good : Moral Choice in Conflict Situations, edited by Paul Ramsey, 7-53. Chicago: Loyola University Press.
Mead, George Herbert, 1863-1931. 1934. Mind, Self & Society from the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. Chicago: The University of Chicago press.
Moltmann, Jurgen. 1974. The Crucified God; the Cross of Christ as the Foundation and Criticism of Christian Theology. New York: Harper & Row.
Murdoch, Iris. 1970. The Sovereignty of Good. London: Ark Paperbacks.
Nelson, Carl Ellis, 1916-2011. 1978. Don't Let Your Conscience be Your Guide. New York: Paulist Press.
Niebuhr, Reinhold, 1892-1971. 2001. Moral Man and Immoral Society : A Study in Ethics and Politics. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press.
Oxley, Julinna C. 2011. The Moral Dimensions of Empathy : Limits and Applications in Ethical Theory and Practice. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire ; New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Patrick, Anne E. 1996. Liberating Conscience : Feminist Explorations in Catholic Moral Theology. New York: Continuum.
Pierce, C. A. 1955. Conscience in the New Testament : A Study of Syneidesis in the New Testament, in the Light of its Sources and with Particular Reference to St. Paul, with some Observations regarding its Pastoral Relevance Today. London: SCM Press.
Pollack, Kenneth M. 2011. The Arab Awakening : America and the Transformation of the Middle East. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Pope John, Paul,II. 1995. Evangelium Vitae. Rome: Rome Vatican.
Ramsey, Paul. 1978. "Incommensurability and Indeterminancy in Moral Choice." In Doing Evil to Achieve Good : Moral Choice in Conflict Situations, edited by Paul Ramsey, 69-144. Chicago: Loyola University Press.
Ratzinger, Joseph. "Conscience and Truth." In Catholic Conscience Foundation Adn Formation: Proceedings of the Tenth Bishops' Workshop; Dallas, TX, 7-27. Braintree, MA: Pope John XXIII Center.
Rauch, Mikele. 2009. Healing the Soul After Religious Abuse: The Dark Heaven of Recovery. Westport: Praeger.
Rothschild, Babette. 2000. The Body Remembers : The Psychophysiology of Trauma and Trauma Treatment. New York: Norton.
Sedmak, Clemens, 1971-. 2002. "Doing Local Theology : A Guide for Artisans of a New Humanity." In , 5-20. Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis Books.
Spohn, William C. and Thomas A. Byrnes. 1996. "Knowledge of Self and Knowledge of God: A Reconstructed Empiricist Interpretation." In Christian Ethics : Problems and Prospects, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and James F. Childress, 119-33. Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.
Spohn, William C. 2000. "Conscience and Moral Development." Theological Studies 61 (1): 122-138.
Stolberg, Sheryl Gay. 2011. "Shy U.S. Intellectual Created Playbook used in a Revolution." New York Times, February 17, 2011, 1.
Tamez, Elsa. 2012. "Women's Leadership in the New Testament." In Gender in Theology, Spirituality and Practice, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and Diego Irarrázaval. 2012/4 ed. London: SCM Press.
Taylor, Charles, 1931-. 1989. Sources of the Self : The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Traina, Christina L. H. 1996. "Creating a Global Discourse in a Pluralist World: Strategies from Environmental Ethics." In Christian Ethics : Problems and Prospects, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and James F. Childress, 250-64. Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.
Vischer, Robert K. 2010. Conscience and the Common Good : Reclaiming the Space between Person and State. Cambridge ; New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wacker, Marie Theres. 2012. "Torah for Women, Confusing Relations and a Winged Deity." In Gender in Theology, Spirituality and Practice, edited by Lisa Sowle Cahill and Diego Irarrázaval. Vol. 4. London: London : SCM Press.




[1] Pope John Paul II Centesimus anus (on the Hundredth Anniversary of Rerum novarum), 23,25, &52, in Catholic Social Thought: The Documentary Heriage, Maryknoll, NY, 1992